banner
 

Timpanaro, Marx, Engels

Of Materialism and Pessimism

Ramkrishna Bhattacharya

One of the novel and surprising concepts proposed by Sebastiano Timpanaro (1923-2000), the well-known Marxist philologist-cum-philosopher, is that of 'materialist pessimism'. His plea is to recognize this concept as a part of the Marxist worldview. Time and again he comes back to it in his book, Sul Materialismo (1970, translated as On Materialism with an Introduction to the English edition). What follows below is intended to critique his view in some detail.

Optimism is generally accepted to be inherent in Marxism, although its founding fathers, Marx and Engels, never declared it in so many words. Engels in his Anti-Duhring somewhat ecstatically declared : 'It (sc. socialism) is humanity's leap from the realm of necessity into the realm of freedom' (p.344).[1] Such a statement might suggest to the unwary reader the negation of necessity, of specific patterns of causation as a whole. Marx in Capital was more cautious in his formulation although he used the same terms:

'The realm of freedom really begins only where labour determined by necessity and external expediency ends; it lies by its very nature beyond the sphere of material production proper....The true realm of freedom, the development of human power as an end in itself begins beyond it, though it can only flourish with this realm of necessity as its basis.' (3: pp.958-59)

The coming into being of a just and equitable social system free from exploitation and subjugation cannot but be deemed as an optimistic vision. The end of the long era of class society will release enormous energy in humankind and open up new vistas of peace and plenty. Then why does Timpanaro raise the issue of pessimism, whether materialist or not?

Timpanaro has no quarrel with Marx's optimistic vision. However, keeping in mind the entity of man in two planes, social and natural, he observes:

'[T]he juxtaposition of a historical and social optimism (communism as a now certain goal of human history, even if the price paid with Stalinism seemed even at that time excessive to many of us, despite our inability to see any alternative to Stalinism other than a social-democratic one) and a pessimism with respect to nature's oppression of man, which would continue to be a cause of urihappiness even in communist society.' (pp.10-11)

By 'nature's oppression of man' Timpanaro means the three archetypal enemies of humans, nay of all living beings, imposed by nature: disease, old age, and death. More than 2500 years ago one young Indian prince also realized the weight of these three and renounced his home to find a remedy. He is said to have found a way to overcome these three by dint of following the Itfe of a recluse and developing through meditation an outlook of his own. His self-realization led to the gaining of bodhi, enlightenment. He was subsequently known as Gautama Buddha, Gautama the Enlightened One.

Timpanaro does not think in terms of any illusory emancipation from the clutch of the three adversaries. Hence he prefers to call his view 'materialist pessimism', for there is no real escape from them. Hurnans have to submit to the scourge resulting from disease, old age, and finally the inevitability of the cessation of life. Whether in the pre-class society or the class society or the classless society, these three enemies will always dog the footsteps of humans, irrespective of all other differences that mark off one individual from the other. It is the forced admission of the inevitability of the human condition that makes Timpanaro believe that, instead of attempting to find any escape route, humans must accept 'man's biological frailty' (p. 18). He further observes: '"Physical ill"... cannot be ascribed solely to bad social arrangements; it has its zone of autonomous and invincible reality' (p.20). He cautions:

'To maintain that, since the 'biological' is always presented to us as mediated by the 'social', the 'biological' is nothing and the 'social' is everything, would once again be idealist sophistry. If we make it ours, how are we to defend ourselves from those who will in turn maintain that, since all reality (including economic and social reality) is knowable only through language (or through the thinking mind), language (or the thinking mind) is the sole reality, and all the rest is abstraction?' (p.45)

Using the terms coined by Antonio Labriola (1843-1904), one of the pioneers of Marxist studies in Italy, Timpanaro speaks of the 'conditioning' that the 'natural terrain' exercises over humans even after the formation and development of the 'artificial terrain' (p.46). But the issue of death, as envisaged by Timpanaro, is not confined to living beings. Since change is the only immutable factor in nature, 'all that comes into being deserves to perish'. This aphoristic sentence, although spoken by an 'unreliable witness', Mephistopheles, in Goethe's Faust (Part I, scene 3), was a favourite with Engels. It led him to anticipate not just the extinction of the human species but the end of the world itself. With the loss of their natural habitat, all denizens of this planet (including humans) will also perish and whatever had been achieved not only in the class society but also in the classless society will also disappear with them. Timpanaro notes that Engels was quite eloquent in this respect (p.98). In his Anti-Duhring Engels paid handsome tribute to Charles Fourier (1772-1837), a remarkable French Utopian socialist, for having handled 'dialectics in the same masterly way as his contemporary Hegel' (p.315). What makes Engels pay such a tribute to Fourier? Engels explains:

'Using these same dialectics, he (sc. Fourier) argues against the talk about illimitable human perfectibility, that every historical phase has its period of ascent and also its period of descent, and he applies this observation to the future of the whole human race. As Kant introduced into natural science the idea of the ultimate destruction of the earth, Fourier introduced into historical science that of the ultimate destruction of the human race.' (p.315).[2]

Timpanaro further refers to a passage in Engels's Dialectics of Nature which, he thinks, gives 'a picture of the future end of our world in which a tragic sense (though it is a serenely tragic sense) about the destiny of mankind predominates' (p.98). The passage in Dialectics of Nature runs as follows :

'Nevertheless, "all that comes into being deserves to perish". Millions of years may elapse, hundreds of thousands of generations be born and die, but inexorably the time will come when the declining warmth of the sun will no longer suffice to melt the ice thrusting itself forward from the poles; when the human race, crowding more and more about the equator, will finally no longer find even there enough heat for life; when gradually even the last trace of organic life will vanish; and the earth, an extinct frozen globe like the moon, will circle in deepest darkness and in an ever narrower orbit about the equally extinct sun, and at last fall into it. Other planets will have preceded it, others will follow it; instead of the bright, warm solar system with its harmonious arrangement of members, only a cold, dead sphere will still pursue its lonely path through universal space. And what will happen to our solar system will happen sooner or later to all the other systems of our island universe; it will happen to all the other innumerable island universes, even to those the light of which will never reach the earth while there is a living human eye to receive it.' (pp.35-36)

One can see how 'this Lucretian theme of the end of the world' (p.99) enables Timpanaro to compare Engels's sentences with the close of an ode, Sumonte Mario by Giosue Carducci (1836-1907) :
...till man's exhausted progeny
Confined beneath the equator
By the call of fleeting warmth
Has a single female, one man.
Timpanaro admits that no two authors could be more unlike each other than Carducci and Engels and there is no possibility of one deriving from the other. Despite these hard facts, Timpanaro says, 'It represents further evidence of the wide diffusion of this theme among even the most diverse areas of European culture in the late nineteenth century.' (p.99)

Not only Carducci but also Giacomo Leopardi (1798-1837), another Italian poet, is brought in to reinforce the theme of pessimism. Leopardi's pessimism, Timpanaro asserts, is 'radically different' from that of all earlier romantics and existentialists from Schopenhauer to Kierkegaard. But Timpa-naro makes a distinction between Leopardi's idea of 'materialist pessimism' and the pessimism of all the central European thinkers. All of them had 'an anti-materialist, anti-Enlightenment, anti-jacobin orientation, and, as expected, all end up in, or at least tend towards, more or less exclusively religious positions' (p. 19), whereas Leopardi's pessimism flowed in a different terrain.

Timpanaro also warns his readers that he does not propose 'yet another marriage of Marxism and "Frankfurt" pessimism, of existentialist or Freudian ancestry' (p. 18). His conception of materialist pessimism, he claims, is derived from the classics of Marxism itself and, notwithstanding such pessimism, the struggle for the betterment of humanity will continue.

What exactly is meant by optimism and pessimism? Without bothering about exact definitions, let us take it for granted that they represent two diametrically opposite points of view: the first encourages hope for future betterment, the other, despair at the present state of affairs and disbelief in any change for the better in future. The fact is that optimism, in order to be realistic, must set limits to its visions. Only a naive optimist would believe in limitless progress and unhindered development. The course of history, a true optimist knows, has both ascending and descending curves, as Fourier noted (see above). French Enlightenment thinkers, like their predecessors during the Renaissance in Europe, used to believe in the potential of every individual to do everything and anything.[3]

Marx, on the other hand, understood that every person has his or her own limitations and, therefore, even in the communist society he did not expect everyone to contribute in equal measures to social welfare. That is why he spoke of 'from each according to his ability to each according to his needs'. In the Critique of the Gotha Programme, Marx also emphasized that the needs of every person cannot be the same: some will need more, some less:
'Further, one worker is married, another not; one has more children than another, and so on and so forth. Thus, with an equal performance of labour, and hence an equal share in the social consumption fund, one will in fact receive more than another, one will be richer than another, and so on. To avoid all these defects, right instead of being equal would have to be unequal.' (p.22)

Therefore, the distribution of products even in a socialist society would be equitable, not equal. Only simple-minded egalitarians, well-intentioned but quite innocent of reality, demand equality in the area of distribution. Equality can only imply equality of rights and opportunities (as opposed to hereditary rights and privileges enjoyed by the gentry in the pre-capitalist eras), nothing else.

In an article entitled 'Junius Pamphlet' (written on July 16, 1916 and published in October 1916) Lenin too once cautioned naive optimists : 'It is undialectical, unscientific, and theoretically wrong to regard the course of world history as smooth and always in a forward direction without occasional gigantic leaps back' (1974 p.310. Emphasis added). The words seem to echo what Engels in Anti-Duhring said about Fourier's outlook and his Hegel-like mastery of dialectics (quoted above).

Notwithstanding this very practical view Lenin did assert: 'Progress, if we leave out for the moment the possibility of temporary steps backward, can be made only in the direction of socialist society, only in the direction of the socialist revolution.' (1974: p.316. Emphases in the original)

And the true socialist society will not appear immediately after the socialist revolution; it will take time. One should be prepared for facing 'occasional gigantic leaps back' at every step. In any case, there will be a first stage when the society can ensure only this much: 'from each according to his ability, to each according to his work.' After traversing a long way humankind will reach the second stage. Marx in his Critique of the Gotha Programme said :

'In a higher phase of communist society, after the enslaving subordination of the individual to the division of labour, and therewith also the antithesis between mental and physical labour, has vanished; after labour has become not only a means of life but life's prime want; after the productive forces have also increased with the all-around development of the individual, and all the springs of co-operative wealth flow more abundantly -- only then can the narrow horizon of bourgeois right be crossed in its entirety and society inscribe on its banners: From each according to his ability, to each according to his needs!' (p.22)

The transition from the first stage to this second, higher stage too cannot be accomplished rapidly, however much one may wish for it. Necessary time has to be allowed for the realization of such a society. Humankind will have miles to go before it can reach there. If an over-optimist turns pessimist because of the delay in reaching the higher stage, the person is only to be pitied.

When Engels spoke of 'the ultimate extinction of humanity', he was not at all being pessimistic. He accepted the fact quite calmly as something inevitable, and as unavoidable as the death of every single individual member of the human species (and of every other species which has animal as its genus). When Marx spoke of 'a higher phase of communist society', he was not being optimistic to the extent that humans will then be able to overcome the perils of old age, disease, and death. The natural or biological terrain was not at issue. Keeping into mind the possibility, nay the certainty of the ultimate setback, Marxists take upon themselves the task of studying human society, a human construct, and seek to transform the world.

Limitless progress (in which even a Utopian socialist like Fourier did not believe) is a grand idea, but it has to be understood in terms of the limited nature of humankind. Humans do not have wings but that does not mean that they can never move in air. Aeroplanes were invented to overcome the 'natural' limitation. What mythographers imagined could not go beyond the limits of their experience. The Greeks conceived of Daedalus and his son, Icarus, flying with artificial wings. The wings closely resembled those of birds with the difference that they had to be attached to the body with wax. Quite naturally, when Icarus, defying his father's advice, soared higher and higher, the wax got melted by the heat of the sun. Consequently, he fell down and died. Apparently, the mythographers too knew or rather felt that flying like birds in their own fashion was not destined for humans. Indian mythographers, on the other hand, conceived the idea of a chariot with wings. Such a chariot, however, was meant for Indra, the king of the gods or for Kubera, a demi-god in charge of wealth lying underground. Royalties like Rama (as said in the Uttarakanda of the Ramayana) or Dushyanta (as stated in Kalidasa's play, Abhijnana-Sakutalam, The Signet Ring of Sakuntala) were sometimes offered the service of such aerial chariots, but that was all. Common humans were excluded from such a privilege. There was always a belief underlying such fancies that flying was after all something to be wished for but never to be attained. However, by inventing the aeroplane, all limits set by nature in this sphere were successfully bypassed. What was not supposed to happen eventually did happen, not however by defying necessity but by appreciating or recognizing it (in the sense of getting insight into it) and circumventing it by other means.[4]

Nevertheless, all limitations set by nature cannot be overcome or subverted or bypassed by inventing novel gadgets. The three archetypal enemies, namely, old age, disease, and death, are of such kind. Thanks to the giant strides made in the world of medicine and surgery, human longevity has been immensely extended. Yet immortality is a dream till now. The fanciful idea of 'the philosopher's stone' or that strange 'elixir of life' that would ensure immortality drove hundreds, if not thousands, of medieval alchemists to search for such magic objects. Yet it was no better than a wild goose chase. Neither old age nor death nor disease can as yet be exterminated, although old age can be made more bearable than before; even such diseases that had been regarded as incurable in the past can now be cured to a large extent, and death too in some cases at least can be less painful than it had been even a few years back. Further inventions in medicine and surgery may bring farther consolations and comforts which people cannot conceive at the present juncture, but such faith in further improvements is not at all unjustified.

Recognizing the inevitability of the presence of the three inescapable adversaries of humankind need not lead to pessimism. On the contrary, a stoic-like acceptance of decay and death is to be strongly recommended for every rationalist. Death after all is not something for which man alone is predestined. Species preservation, like self-preservation, is instinctive to all animals, including man. New progeny is bound to appear in every generation. Without death, the population of the whole living world would go on increasing, so much so that there would inevitably be a population explosion. It would then cause famines and disasters and lead to inconceivable chaos. Death is necessary in order to make room for the next generations: the old must yield to the new. Thus decay and death are a necessary part of nature's schema. There is nothing to be pessimistic about it.

It is rather surprising that Timpanaro who, against the concerted campaign of some self-styled Marxologists, defended Engels's rightful claim to be regarded as a co-founder of Marxism, did not care to remember what Engels had said about life and death in his Dialectics of Nature. Here is the whole passage :
'Life and death. Already no physiology is held to be scientific if it does not consider death as an essential element of life (note, Hegel, Enzyklopadie, I, pp. 152-53), the negation of life as being essentially contained in life itself, so that life is always thought of in relation to its necessary result, death, which is always contained in it in germ. The dialectical conception of life is nothing more than this. But for anyone who has once understood this, all talk of the immortality of the soul is done away with. Death is either the dissolution of the organic body, leaving nothing behind but the chemical constituents that formed its substance, or it leaves behind a vital principle, more or less the soul, that then survives all living organisms, and not only human beings. Here, therefore, by means of dialectics, simply becoming clear about the nature of life and death suffices to abolish an ancient superstition. Living means dying.' (p.295)

It is rewarding to remember in this connection that words like optimism and pessimism did not appear in English (and presumably in other modern languages too) before the eighteenth century. In addition to the philosophical significance endowed to the word 'optimism' by G W Leibniz (1646-1716), it has come to mean a belief in the 'ultimate predominance of good over evil in the universe,' as said by Emerson in 1841. Optimism further suggests a 'disposition to hope for the best or to look on the bright side of things; general tendency to take a favourable view of circumstances or prospects.' Pessimism similarly emerged as a tendency to look exclusively at the dark side of things. This word too received a philosophical coating in the hands of Arthur Schopenhauer (1788-1860) and others in the early nineteenth century.[5]

Neither unbounded optimism nor all-out pessimism can be a part of the lebensphilosophie (philosophy of life) of a rationalist. His or her optimism too is not naive, it is always critical. Critical optimism urges all to cut their coat according to their cloth, at least for the present. Utopias no doubt played and will play a historical role by helping humans to stretch out their hands for what is badly needed but not available.[7] Many new inventions that have now become part of human beings daily life were first projected in the utopias, not just in Thomas More's classic, Utopia (first published in 1523), but in much earlier times, in the works of Greek and Latin authors.[8]

One may in this connection think of the (e)utopia (both 'good place' and 'no-place') of ancient India, the mythical land called Uttarakuru. Right from the Vedic times down to the epics and the Puranas, one reads of this land of plenty and prosperity.[9]  Uttarakuru differs from the then world (and today's world too) in two major respects: (a) there is no private property (amama, literally, not-mine. Cf. Latin meum and teum, mine and yours), and (b) there is no marriage (aparigraha) there. These two features reflect the justified yearning for the abolition of private property and of patriarchy which imposes marriage as the only approved form of male-female sexual relationship. The second is not unrelated to the first for marriage entails the domination of husband over wife, and inheritance of property from fathers to their legitimate children. Thus the legend of Uttarakuru points to a valid form of society, free from the bondage of private property and the laws of inheritance. The demand for the abolition of these two evils is nothing impossible to achieve. The socialist programme proposed by such late eighteenth and early nineteenth-century social thinkers as Fourier, Owen, St Simon and others, culminating in the Communist Manifesto by Marx and Engels (1848) leads to the same direction.

Timpanaro's concept of pessimism, drawn from Carducci and Leopardi, seems to be a yearning for something which is against the laws of nature. The concept of pessimism is thereby overextended: it transgresses the limits set by nature, 'the natural terrain' to which humans belong and must belong. Instead of thinking in terms of either optimism or pessimism, a rationalist should rather pay more attention to what is necessary and achievable, whether in the short or in the long run, rather than crave for what is neither required nor probable to happen.

Notes and References :
1.    In the extract from Anti-Duhring published as a separate book, Socialism : Utopian and Scientific, the sentence reads: 'It is the ascent of man from the kingdom of necessity to the kingdom of freedom' (p.82).
2.   This translation by Clemens Palme Dutt, as found in the Moscow edition (1977), differs a little from what has been reproduced in the English rendering of Timpanaro's book (p.98) from the New York edition of Anti-Duhring (1940 p.285).
3.   Speaking of the 'giants' who appeared during the Renaissance, Engels said: The heroes of that time were not yet in thrall to the division of labour, the restricting influence of which, with its production of one-sidedness we so often notice in their successors' (1982 p.22). In Holy Family Marx and Engels observed: There is no need for any great penetration to see from the teaching of materialism on the original goodness of man, the omnipotence of experience, habit and education, and influence of environment on man, ..how necessarily materialism is connected with communism and socialism' (1975 p.154).
4.   Engels in Anti-Duhring quoted from Hegel a sentence, '...ist die Freiheit, die Einsicht in die Notwindigkeit'. Emile Burns translated it as 'Freedom is the appreciation of necessity' (Moscow ed. p.140). But there is 'recognition' in place of 'appreciation' in the Peking translation (p.144). In the Moscow translation of Lenin's Materialism and Empirio-Criticism, in rendering the same sentence from Engels/Hegel, there is 'recognition' in the New York edition of Lenin's Collected Works (vol. 13 p. 154) whereas in the Moscow edition of the same (vol.14 p. 187) and in the text published in separate book form (n.d., p. 190) there is 'appreciation'. All this has caused and still causes a lot of confusion. John Somerville in a seminal essay suggested: The word "insight," much closer to 'Einsicht" than is "appreciation" or "recognition," pointedly suggests, as part of its meaning, a basis for better action and control (which was central to Engels' thought)...' (p.20).
5.   All references are to the Oxford English Dictionary (compact edition).
6.   See Bogomolov, pp.52, 152. The source may be Seneca, p.50 n17 (as stated in Wikipedia).
7.   For the importance of Utopias in history see Morton, and Bloch.
8.   Literally Utopia in Latin signifies 'no place', utopia.The generic name of all such imaginary lands has been adapted from the title of More's work. Some specimens of earlier and later utopias are available in J W Johnson (ed.), and More's Utopia (ed. R M Adams).
9. See R Bhattacharya 2000 and 2004 for details.

Frontier
Vol. 46, No. 34, Mar 2 - 8, 2014